[I should dedicate this post to Ray Davis, without whom I couldn't have written it. But who dedicates posts to people? That said, one item he linked to deserves special consideration, as it proves stuff written years ago possesses commensurate quantities of wit and intelligence to things posted within the past 24 hours. Also, I remember now why I miss him, and regret again whatever part I played in driving him away. But enough of that. To the post!]
Today is one of those rare days I regret not being a "professional" blogger. I have so much on my plate—so much which seems urgent—that I hardly know where to focus my attention. So I'll let someone else decide:
Following Ray's links, I stumbled on Jonah Lehrer's lukewarm defense of Malcolm Gladwell's Blink. Unbeknownst to you, dear readers, I wrote a very similar account not only of Gladwell's book, but of all popular neuroscience, in which I declared sublime those
"meta-" moments that only books about human consciousness provide. For example:
Picture in your mind the face of Marilyn Monroe. Ready? You just used your fusiform gyrus. (219)
Blows my mind every time. I love books that produce the physiological effects they describe in the act of describing them. Steven Pinker's explanations may be just-so stories, but the processes for which they account are solid science. When he says "when Y, then X," you can be certain that when a guy confronts Y, his brain explodes with X—even if X didn't develop because a greater percentage of monkeys who could scuttle up trees one-handed in the rain survived than didn't.
Now, thanks to Lehrer, I can trumpet Timothy D. Wilson's Strangers to Ourselves too, only without all the caveats Gladwell inspired. For one, the complaint about the dearth of footnotes evaporates. Wilson documents the studies he cites, and I've spent the past couple of hours browsing through those articles. I'm surprised by what I've found.
More often than not, the claims the authors propound are far more radical than those Wilson attributes to them. He tones them down, renders them more palatable to the regnant orthodoxy. Which is odd. Most popular science writers inflate the importance of the research they cite in order to grab the reader's attention. (Norman Holland and Steven Pinker spring to mind.) Why does Wilson take the opposite tack?
I'm not sure. It may be constitutional. Anyone who can "teach the conflicts"—that is the first non-paywalled link I could find—the way Wilson can possesses the rare talent for fairness in the face of vicious intellectual bluster. He presents all arguments—the psychoanalytic included—in their strongest forms and that, apparently, entails deflating the work of contemporary cognitive science while inflating the importance of psychoanalytic "findings." With the exception of Occam's Razor's appearance on page 79 —there is "no need to introduce additional theoretical constructs"—psychoanalysis seems a viable, if frequently problematic, alternative to contemporary cognitive theory. (Which, of course, merely validates the "scientific" quality of Freud's intuitions. Not that Wilson says that, mind you, only that he doesn't refute it vehemently enough.)
In short, Wilson's book is diplomatic, albeit devestatingly so. What do I mean? His rhetoric aside, one cannot read the first 130 pages and not immediately dismiss psychoanalysis. While some of the mechanisms of the modern brain resemble their psychoanalytic counterparts, they share neither their power nor etiology. And etiology is of fundamental, foundational importance to psychoanalytic thinking. Does this mean that the psychoanalytic model is wholly irrelevant to the study of cultural or literature?
No. (Although this may convince you otherwise.) I'll write more once I've finished the book and have time to sort through my new theory of the importance of the obsolete philosophies of mind to study of literature. (Sure, I sound dismissive, but the strange thing is, I'm not.)
UPDATE: I included no accounts of the fascinating studies Wilson cites in his book. I'm not sure why, other than the vanilla excuse that I am, on occasion, not all that bright. So I present those tomorrow, after I've finished the book. (It only arrived around 3 p.m. Who can read a 300 page book in two hours?)
Scott, you didn't drive me away! I'm right here, man!
Except I gotta go to work now. More later; I like the approach you're taking here a lot -- given its cultural importance there's not nearly enough serious criticism of popular science as a genre, and your proposed formula doesn't sound at all dismissive to me.
Posted by: Ray Davis | Friday, 14 July 2006 at 08:40 AM
"Picture in your mind the face of Marilyn Monroe. Ready? You just used your fusiform gyrus. (219)"
Doesn't "fusiform gyrus" just mean a "form that pours out images"? Through a brain-scan, I suppose, you realize that the "fusiform gyrus" always lights up when you ask the subject to picture Marilyn Monroe. Of course, you don't know that it's called the "fusiform gyrus" when you start out. You suppose this only after you notice the correlation -- and then you name this area of the brain "that which pours out images". Then someone can come along and explain the process to me, saying, "You just used your fusiform gyrus". But what does that mean, that I "used" it? It seems to me kind of like saying, "Whenever you push that button, and only when you push that button, Song X plays" -- but it doesn't explain by what mechanism the button plays Song X -- and I don't know how it could. How could you ever "see" that sort of thing? The best you can do is say that certain patterns in the brain correlate to certain experiences by way of "meaning" -- but you can't use the same technique to explain what "meaning" is because you would end up saying, "Well whenever this pattern occurs in the brain, we conclude that it means there is meaning".
Posted by: Alex Leibowitz | Friday, 14 July 2006 at 06:15 PM
So what someone is going to do is explain, I hope, "No Alex, you've got it all wrong! It's not through correlation of patterns with experiences that we come to these conclusions at all!"
Posted by: Alex Leibowitz | Friday, 14 July 2006 at 06:20 PM
This is a notoriously tricky problem, and a sure way to prod a couple of neuroscientists into a quarrel. They can't even come to a consensus as to whether consciousness is epiphenomenal or not. That said, neuroscientists can explain more than mere correlation; they can talk about the nature of the electrical and biochemical interaction which distinguishes one process from another, even if they're localized in the same area of the brain. I think they can avoid the circularity you point out here by simple empiricism. Another way to say that is humanities types (and humanistically-inclined scientists) tend to ask too much of evidence, and too early. (Thus the problem with Pinker identified above.) We want an infant science to enable us to produce claims we can only reasonably expect from a mature one; hence, the lack of sophistication relative to psychoanalysis, &c.
Posted by: Scott Eric Kaufman | Saturday, 15 July 2006 at 08:38 AM
Alex, is the problem that you think that your thoughts are created by your soul, or something like that? Because if you grant that thoughts are created by biochemical / electrical impulses flowing along nerves, then you have to accept that eventually neurologists will generally trace out which areas of the brain they come from.
The mechanism in "if you push a button, Song X plays" is not mysterious. Even if you know nothing about the particular box playing the song, you have to accept that an engineer who knows the technology involved could trace out the mechanisms at each step of the chain from button press to song playing.
Since human beings designed and built song-playing boxes, this is not really a good example. The difference is that we didn't design and build brains, and we don't really know large parts of how they work. But we will, presumably, unless science stops working as it has. It seems like you have duplicated in technology the in my opinion very poor theological argument about "the god of the gaps".
Posted by: Rich Puchalsky | Saturday, 15 July 2006 at 09:38 AM
Rich --
I hope you don't think my dislike of science is a sin! Or worse something irrational! Surely it's something we can get to the bottom of, something to which we can assign an explanation and through the use of properly devised antidotes (I almost said anecdotes), correct. I find my propensities disturbing also -- it isn't pleasant to be on *this* side of the argument, especially when the neo-empiricists are winning the day!
But there *is* something strange going on: namely, consciousness is conscious of itself. How can that be? And I think the song-box example works if you keep in mind that it isn't *pushing the button* that causes the music -- there's some other process hidden inside the box.
But then there's another issue, which is: how the vibrations get translated into the experience of music? Now there's a simple side to the problem, as I think about it, which is that you can devise a symbol scheme that represents vibrations in the air and "write" that on a disk. Then you just need a media that translates the symbols back into vibrations.
But the ear needs to translate the vibrations into experience, and that seems to me to involve the emergence of consciousness from something purely material. That is to say (I'm thinking out loud here, so do forgive the convolution) when I'm conscious of a record playing, I'm conscious of more than just the sounds I hear -- I also am conscious that I hear those sounds. That, I think, is more difficult to explain.
And I don't believe in God, nor am I vouching for the immortality of the soul, so I have no overt interest in advancing a theology.
Posted by: Alex Leibowitz | Saturday, 15 July 2006 at 12:12 PM
That, however, is something that can be explained via the mental module theory of contemporary cognitive science. You have a selective attention, certainly, but you have one module which converts the raw phonetic material of spoken language into phonemic data you recognize as language; another which apprehends the aural patterns in the music you're listening to; not to mention a whole slew of others doing other things entirely—prioperception of your body's spatial orientation, &c. These modules have to run simultaneously; the queston cognitive scientists quarrel over is whether consciousness precedes them, or whether it's produced by them. It's an important question, but also one which matters less than you think, since ever there you're employing a fuzzy notion of what constitutes "consciousness." It's reflexive and not, say, deliberative; and those systems work differently (as evidenced by the fact that people who've suffered brain damage which impairs their ability to process reflexives still retain all other higher cognitive functions).
Posted by: Scott Eric Kaufman | Saturday, 15 July 2006 at 12:25 PM
I suppose my question is what the meaning of "conversion" is in this case?
Posted by: Alex Leibowitz | Saturday, 15 July 2006 at 02:31 PM